Thursday, July 22, 2010

"I ain't afraid of no ghosts": My reading of Derrida's _Specters of Marx_



Why is Derrida’s then-highly-anticipated official comment on something called “Marxism” and his statement about the future of politics in the age of global capitalism haunted by the specter of the fictional character Hamlet? That Marx himself was an avid admirer of Shakespeare is no secret and that Derrida’s quasi-philosophical explorations often draw from various works of literary fiction is something we have come to expect. I think, though, that not only does a cross-reading Shakespeare’s text allow Derrida an entry point for introducing/expanding a number of concepts that will be fleshed out in his meditation of Marx, but—more than this—I think the simultaneous discussion of the themes of non-temporal time, “hauntology,” undeciability, and justice in the differing texts allows Derrida to make an implicit connection between literature and “the political”; between “deconstruction” and politics. While I would argue that already in the “early” Derrida (I think here of _Of Grammatology_) language and literature are always inherently political, the stakes become much higher when Derrida is confronted with answering the specific questions of his relationship to the Marxian tradition and the political import of his methods of reading as it relates to the world-wide political turmoil of our age. Let’s see how Derrida approaches these questions.

The text of _Specters of Marx: The State of Debt, the Work of Mourning, and the New International_ grew out of Derrida’s lectures a 1993 conference “Whither Marxism? Global Crises in International Perspective” held at University of California, Riverside. Scholars and critics across national and disciplinary boundaries gathered to approach the question—essentially—“What do we do with Marx now?” That is, in the aftermath of the crumbling of the Berlin wall in 1989, the economic incorporation of Europe a few years later, the ongoing economic growth of Eastern markets, and Francis Fukuyama’s prediction the eventual global triumph of political and economic liberalism and the “end of history” (_The End of History and the Last Man_,1992), scholars who did ,and did not, claim to be followers of Marx found themselves pressed with answering how relevant Marx’s theories remained in this economic/political landscape so different from Marx’s. The question is rephrased in Derrida’s opening address at the conference, “what have we inherited from Marx?” The term “inheritance” is a loaded one for Derrida, along with words and phrases like “the gift,” “the proper name,” “friendship,” and “hospitality,” themes that Derrida continues to revisit and complicate in this period of his writings. For my purposes here, I will not expand at length on Derrida’s conception of what it means to inherit (other than to note, for Derrida it will mean the call to a certain “responsibility”)—but rather I’d like to touch on a few relevant themes that run through the lectures, before gesturing towards some of the most vehement responses of critics to this text.




“The time is out of joint,” declares the melancholy prince in I.v of _Hamlet_, after swearing his commitment to “remember” at the foot of his father’s ghost. Derrida uses the motif of a disjointed temporality to introduce both the relationship of us “heirs” of Marx as well the necessary condition for justice—one will notice that these two themes, the possibilities of “Marx” and justice today, are never separate in Derrida’s reading. Hamlet laments, and curses, the fact that his father’s ghost has called him to put time back into joint by avenging his death. This is because “revenge” would call for Hamlet to inherit, in one way or another, the crimes of the past, and to bring that cycle of crime and punishment into the future. The weight of the call for Hamlet’s revenge, while pondered in the present diegetic world of the play, rests firmly in the relationship between the past event and the murder to be committed in the future; the decision that Hamlet wrestles with throughout is the gap between these two temporal sites. He is called to fix the history that came before, and this, claims Derrdia, is the position of the heirs of Marx. But readers of revenge tragedy will recognize the strange temporality of the act of vengeance—something I think Derrida would liken to a “general” rather than “restricted” economy—which per force is not entirely compensatory. Rather than putting “time back in joint,” the act of revenge in such dramas can never really compensate for the crime; the dead are not made present again, and a whole new cycle of crimes and punishments is engendered. It is, in fact, two articulations of absence, that of what has passed and that of what is to come. Hamlet curses because in this case justice is born of vengeance, and Derrida interrogates such a notion calling for instead an “incalculable” justice that exceeds the law of retribution, an understanding of justice that goes beyond “faults” of the past. As developed elsewhere (Cf. _Politics of Friendship_, _The Gift of Death_) we see Derrida’s notion of a type of “gift without restitution”: “ Beyond right, and still more beyond jurididicism, beyond morality, and still more beyond moralism” (27). One of Derrida’ s major threads here is that we need to re-evaluate our conception of justice as an articulation of presence, because as we have seen, justice is intimately tied to the past and the future: “Otherwise justice risks being reduced once again to juridical-moral rules, norms or representations, within an inevitably totalizing horizon” (28).

In order to understand this very strange temporality, we will need to (at least attempt) to understand what Derrida calls “hauntology” or “spectral logic.” “Hauntology” emphasizes what is NOT present, like the ghost of King Hamlet and Marx for us today. A ghost is never (really,that is corporally) present and it never dies, and therefore it is BEYOND essence as we are accustomed to imagine it. It is both singular in its appearance and multiple in its repeating (through the visitation) since it is the trace of something once present. These are not unfamiliar ideas once we have made acquaintance with Derrida’s lifelong interrogation of a “metaphysics of presence.” This attention to what is not present allows for an interaction with the completely other or total alterity. In short, Derrida wants to replace “ontology” (Being as presence) with “hauntology,” an experience that is open to what is not present, rather what was and what perhaps WILL be. In a characteristic rhetorical flourish, Derrida writes, “ No différance without alterity, no alterity without singularity, no singularity without the here-and-now” (30). This one sentence would take pages to unpack, but I take it to mean that both the deconstructive way of reading and this particular formulation of justice (that we will hear more about below) calls for an opening to the altogether other that is not merely a moment of delay, but an instant promise of singularity, and what makes this promise truly of the “here-and-now” is that is not made based on adherence to reified a priori laws.



And this brings us to a third major thread woven throughout the text: the relationship between undecidability and justice. What draws Hamlet, our inheritance from Marx, and the practice of deconstructive reading together is the question of NOT knowing, through which the possible is related to the impossible through the injunction of “perhaps.” This is the type of phrase, emphasizing “undecidability,” that I think really puts pressure on the possibility for change—if we are not reading careful enough. Derrida writes, “Needless to spell it out here, therefore, still lest to insist on it too heavily: it [both “deconstruction” and Derrida’s proposed notion of justice] is not a taste for the void or for destruction…On the contrary, it is a matter therefore of an ethical and political imperative, an appeal as unconditional as the appeal from which it is not separated” ( 30).

One way to approach this ambiguity in Derrida’s logic is to think about this moment of undeciabliity similar to other “failures” of reason/knowledge that point to something beyond that we see in other philosophical paradigms. I am thinking here, foremost, about the Platonic dialectic, which per force begins with what is “unknown” (better, “not yet known” or not yet made intelligible by Socrates)and proceeds through the process of attaining new knowledge. Speaking of dialectics, there is Hegel, in which the moment of mis-recognition in the coming to be of self-consciousness yields true recognition of oneself and one’s relation to external reality in the _Phenomenology_. The experience of the Kantian sublime is yet another experience in which reason fails, but only to point beyond its own limits to bring the subject a greater encounter of subjectivity. Finally, I think of Freud, for whom it is not understanding of the conscious, rational mind that leads to the uncovering of man’s motivations, but rather that which resists one’s reasonable faculties, the unconscious. My point here is simply that the concept that the failure of certainty or knowledge can lead to something greater, or the idea that through a relationship to what one can’t know one can move beyond to new knowledge, does not start with Derrida.



The text has many very intelligent things to say, that for the sake of brevity, I won’t address here. For instance, Derrida’s close reading of and response to Fukuyama(Chapter 2, which we should note also, this becomes an implicit critique of Kojeve) is well-worth the read and his attentive explication of Marx’s _Capital_ in Chapter 5 (especially on Marx’s “dancing tables” ) is truly a pleasure. Rather, I’d like to take a glance at what become the two related and most controversial elements of these lectures, and some of the criticisms leveled against them, before attempting to see if we still can find any merit in what Derrida is proposing here. These two ideas, which go hand-in-hand, are Derrida’s call for a “mesianism without a messiah” and his proposal of the “New International.”
What exactly is a “messianism without a messiah”? It sure sounds like maintaining a state of constant waiting for something that won’t come, because it doesn’t exist. Essentially, a state of interminable stasis. But, before we judge, let’s listen to Derrida speak:

Now, if there is a spirit of Marxism which I will never be ready to renounce, it is not only the critical idea or the questioning stance…It is even more a certain emancatory an messianic affirmation, a certain experience of the promise that one can try to liberate from any dogmatics and even from any metaphysico-religious determination, from any messianism…To break with the “party form” or with some form of the State or International does not mean to give up every form of practical or effective organization. It is exactly the contrary that matters to us here…The critique belongs to the movement of an experience open to the absolute future of what is coming, that is to say , a necessarily indeterminate, abstract, desert-like experience that is confided, exposed, given up to its waiting for the other and for the event. (89-90)

I take this to mean that “messianism without a messiah” amounts to a constant, vigilant, and radical critique of a way of thinking that is never static because it is always in the process of its own questioning, and never merely a replication of established dogma. A page or so later Derrida calls deconstruction a “radicalization” of a “certain spirit of Marxism” (92), because he is attempting here to radicalize, or free from reified concepts a system of thought that now appears without a future. That is, if we are haunted by the “ghost” of Marx, we are not only inheriting the “crimes of the past” (the failures of Marxist regimes, the mis-reads of Marx throughout the ages), like young Hamlet, BUT we also have a RESPONSIBILTY to the future—a future we cannot make a concrete prediction for when/if it will come, in the same way Hamlet and Horatio cannot be sure the Ghost will return the following night. This too, I think, of what we are to do with our concepts of “democracy” and the “State.” We need to re-configure our conceptions of time and space in order to allow for a “democracy-to-come” and the potential for true justice : “This messianic hesitation does not paralyze any decision, any affirmation, any responsibility. On the contrary, it grants them their elementary condition. It is their very experience” (169). This is facing indeterminacy--and the responsibility--to keep thinking and keep striving for something beyond. Recall that Hamlet’s preservation of indeterminacy is what creates the actual space of the drama.

As anyone can surely imagine, these “political” ideas did not sit well with many, especially many Marxists, who viewed Derrida as proposing something closer to nihilism or his own quasi-transcendentalism, rather than a “radicalization of Marxism.” As a result, Michael Sprinkler pulled together various responses that had appeared in the aftermath of the “Whither Marxism” conference and collected them in one text, under the heading _Ghostly Demarcations: A Symposium on Jacques Derrida’s ‘Specters of Marx’_. In Terry Eagleton’s essay, “Marxism Without Marx,” he essentially asks, “where was Derrida when we needed him” and claims that whether it is through Derrida himself, or any of his “followers”, deconstruction is nothing like Marxism. He claims that Derrida exhibits a “postmodern” desire to never take a stand, rather than a true and effective strategy that could ever apply to reality or history. In, “Reconciling Derrida,” Aijaz Ahmed dubs the politics of deconstruction an “anti-politics” and takes issue with the fact that Derrida’s text is not an analysis, but “performance” (90). Ahmed also claims that Derrida ignores the issue of “class” in his conception of the New International. I think, perhaps, looking briefly at how Derrida responds to these accusations in his essay (the final of the collection) will help shed some light on what we ultimately make of the import of these ideas. [Note that the most of the other essays in this collection are worth a read because of the rich conversation they continue, and Jameson’s contribution—for my money—is very intelligent and does the most “justice” (now such a loaded term!) to Derrida’s text]

Derrida admits, “ In _Specters of Marx_, the presentation of the hypothesis does not present itself, in the proper sense”, but , like Marx’s _Manifesto_ it calls for interpretation and responsibility: “ Without presenting itself in the present, it nevertheless takes a position…that is, the ‘responsibility’ thus assumed- as a transformation” (219). And this responsibility is to commit oneself to PERFORM. This is why we can say that, yes, Ahmed is correct, _Specters_ is a performative text. But his is NOT a negative thing for Derrida; quite the opposite, as this welding together of form and content is the space for change opened up by thinking. This allows then for the “paradoxical transposition” of the famous 11th Thesis on Feuerbach, so that this performative interpretation is “an interpretation that transforms the very thing it interprets” (219). Performativity questions the notion of Being as presence. Against charges that Derrida proposes something anti-political or ventures to ignore issues of class struggle, he responds that after “putting the question into question” (meaning questioning ontology as a measure of self-presence) that “what should come after this deconstruction of Marxist ‘ontology’, in my view, is exactly the opposite of a depoliticization…rather the point, as I see it, of radically re-examining the premises” of any theory of “Marxist” principles, democracy, and the State (221). Derrida does not recommend that one never “takes a stand” on issues of class inequality, but rather that we be ever attentive to what words like “class” and “inequality” mean, and how these meanings shift in every context: “ All this depends, at every instant, on what is urgent in, first and foremost, singular situations and their structural implications. For such assessment, there is, by definition, no pre-existing criterion or absolute calculability” (239). If one wants to champion Marx’s cry for constant attention to “material reality” versus some form of abstract idealism, then what else is Derrida’s suggestion for such an vigilant attention to the real world? This is why messianicity cannot be construed as some abstract, metaphysical Utopia, but “ it refers, in every here and now, to the coming of an eminately real, concrete event” ( 248).

Let’s recall Marx on “estranged labor” in _Capital_. The problem, he says, is that each individual laborer gets grouped into some collective idea of “labor power,” and in the process the particular struggles and material life of each and every man becomes congealed into a giant mass of some ABSTRACT idea of “labor.” How do we change this? By throwing into question the concept of “labor” as such. By re-examining each singular instance as something unique that has ties to a larger overall structure, the structure from which we have accepted our concepts, and our abstract concept of “labor”. This is exactly what Derrida is attempting to do. The idea is not to ignore, eliminate, or sweep under the rug issues of class, but to resist substituting REAL issues under the concept “class.” When “labor” became an abstract concept used to define a certain group of people, something got left out. This too is what has happened to our concepts of “class,” “the State,” and—of course—“Marx.”

Why are we still haunted by Marx? Why do we need to reassess his ideas now? We will recall that the reason so many Marxisms (plural), so many differing opinions on how to read Marx in political, philosophical, and economic terms, exists is because Marx’s prediction for a future stateless, classless society did not have a codified, step-by-step plan. This is why we need to consider a “New” International. When we remained tied to reified ways of thinking that do not adapt to new contexts, temporal shifts, changes in landscapes of all kinds, that is when we are static in a state where true decisions cannot be made. We are like the protagonists of revenge tragedies, stuck in an endless cycle of retribution for a problem that is never solved. Derrida, too, refuses to give us a concrete plan. But we have only to look at texts like _Ghostly Demarcations_ to find evidence that we are talking about these ideas, evaluating and re-evaluating them. And in these conversations about that which we disagree or don’t yet understand, exists the possibility to change the way we think. And by extension, the way we live.

“Thou art a scholar; speak to it, Horatio.”



Tuesday, June 22, 2010

Part II of Notes on Derrida's _Dissemination_




Part 2 : Plato’s Pharmacy
Section I: Derrida “begins” (a loaded term we see, because even the space between the “Outwork” and the start of the explication of Plato is occupied by an epigram, and unnamed sort or mini preface, followed by another prefatory note before the first section) with the claim that Plato’s text is fissured not only through each individual reading ,which produces different interpretations, but from within the words of the text themselves. The entry point for this exploration of linguistic ambiguity: pharmakon, I word I mentioned above simultaneously means “remedy” and “poison.” While the word itself already harbors polysemy within it, we note that any attempt to translate the word “erases” these “resources of ambiguity” and makes “more difficult, if not impossible, and understanding of the context” (97). Derrida highlights the “irreducible difficulty of translation” and makes the claim, “with this problem of translation we will thus be dealing with nothing less than the very problem of the passage into philosophy” (72). What does he mean by this? Derrida’s critique of Western metaphysics will hinge on a questioning of a “metaphysics of presence”—the belief in the primacy of presence over absence and the desire for (and possibility of) immediate access to meaning. So when we look at the process of translation, we see that the translator must make an either/or decision about the “meaning” of a word following a binary logic that neutralizes the play of differences already built into each word. A translation should make us aware of the ABSENCE of the so-called “original” word, and thus the impossibility of such unity in the word itself, but instead translation masquerades as the presence of some unified meaning. This is the problem of Western metaphysics according to Derrida.

Importantly, in the _Phaedrus_, Socrates compares Phaedrus’ written texts to a drug (pharmakon) as we see in Derrida’s reading of the myth of Thoth that Socrates uses to respond to Phaedrus. I won’t recount the myth here (it would be worthwhile to check out this section of _Phaedrus_ or even Derrida’s inclusion of some parts), but an important aspect to become familiar with is that Thoth, the god of writing, brings written letters to the King, and the King denounces writing as inferior to speech, in that speech is the “living” word and is the mechanism of true “memory”, while writing is more like witchcraft and gives only the appearance of true knowledge. Thoth introduces difference into language and “it is to him that the origin of the plurality of languages is attributed” (88). Derrida then traces how the myths surrounding Thoth make him the god of substitution, as when he is called forth to “substitute” or “stand in” for the god Ra. But this process of substitution or supplementation is always one touched by violence: “ Thoth also frequently participates in plots, perfidious intrigues, conspiracies to usurp the throne. He helps the sons do away with the father, the brothers do away with the brother that has become the king” (89). What Derrida sketches out for us, is that—the the act of writing that he presides over as god—Thoth has no essence; he is total supplementarity in both senses that Derrida employs the term: “ The figure of Thoth is thus opposed to its other (father, sun, life, speech, origin, orient etc) but as that which at once supplements and supplants it. Thoth extends or opposes, by repeating or replacing. By the same token, the figure takes shape and takes its shape from the very thing it resists and substitutes for. But it thereby opposes itself, passes into its other, and this messenger-god is truly a god of the absolute passage between opposites” (92-3). It is worth noting that Derrida reminds us writing, as opposed to the “living word” of speech, also becomes associated with death, as Thoth is not only the King’s Master of Books but the keeper of the records of the dead.

The fourth section of Part I, in which Derrida explores the vast web of meanings of the word pharmakon is helpful in approaching the question of author’s intent and agency that has long been a question in “deconstructive” readings. What Derrida makes clear, is that Plato’s “intent” is immaterial because the word pharmakon (and every word for that matter) is part of a complex and diverse system, “among diverse strata and regions of culture” (95). Because all reality is constituted by language, and Plato is of course a member of this reality, then we are simply not able to ask questions about whether the differences implied by the word pharmakon are “involuntary” or “voluntary.” To ask what is the “cause” of these differences or in what “place” they happen actually only points to a problem in the question itself: the question follows a metaphysics of presence that seeks immediate unified meaning and effaces the play of differences inherent in the system of language, of which we are all apart, whether we are conscious of it or not.

In a discussion of “memory” vs. “memorial” (visa vis Plato’s _The Sophist_), Derrida points out that while speech is supposed to be the mechanism of true knowledge via memory, versus the writing of the Sophist who only “mimes” true knowledge in writing, memory itself is already the manifestation—not of presence—but absence: “ memory therefore already needs a sign in order to recall the non-present, with which it is necessarily in relation” (109). That is, memory (read: speech) is already a trace. So why is the idea of memorial or of the supplement so “dangerous” (109)? We will recognize a similar discussion to this one from the explication of Rousseau in _Grammatology_: “ It’s slidings slip in and out of the simple alternative presence/absence. That is the danger” (109). Once the supplement is introduced, the “inside” opens up and a whole chain of replacements is introduced; the unity of the whole is destroyed. And writing, the supplement par excellance, is especially dangerous because it is “the supplement of a supplement, the signifier, the representative of a representative” (109; note, this seems to be Plato’s argument against the 3 times removed truth of poetry in the _Republic_). Derrida notes that “Platonism” is built then on the distinction between signifier and signified and from this opposition constitutes itself as contrary to sophistics, so that “ philosophy and dialectics are determined in the act of determining the other” (112). Here again we see the logic of supplementarity at work.



Section 2
We often make a distinction between “early” Derrida that is more interested in language so to speak, and the “later” Derrida that seems to make a move toward more political issues, though of course this distinction is tenuous at best ,since Derrida never really gives us a concrete political program. However, I would argue that language/writing is ALWAYS political for Derrida, and we see glimmers of this in _Dissemination_. In Plato, Derrida claims, the pharmakon or writing threatens unity, because of its supplementary nature discussed above. Writing, which should have been just an accessory or “excess” has to be put back outside of the system (speech as full presence) that it ruptures. The remedy for Plato is the logos, or dialectics. However, and this is key, dialectics must “call upon the very thing it is expelling, the very surplus it is putting out” (128). What Derrida is getting to here, and what he will show in this section, is that while condemning “myth” or writing as opposed to the true knowledge Plato must always use writing; not in the obvious sense that the dialogues have been recorded and passed down in written form, but that Plato needs poetic language along with the dialectic. He needs metaphor. Derrida does not mention this in his discussion of _Republic_ in this text, but I think we can use this idea to understand why Book X ends in myth, the myth of Er. Plato needs to re-write myth, and this myth blots out the intellectual dialogue that has brought the reader to the end of the text, only to bring her—essentially—back to the beginning . In order for the dialectic to point beyond itself as Plato wishes, it must have recourse to its “opposite” in myth, but in this relationship we see that there is no real opposition between them. Derrida’s reading of _Phaedrus_ could apply to the end of Book X in the _Republic_:
“Socrates ties up into a system all the counts of indictment against the pharmakon of writing at the point at which he adopts his own, in order to uphold it, interpret it, make it explicit, the divine, royal, paternal solar word…Transforming mythos to logos” (134).

But back to politics. In the same way that dialectics needs its other of myth to secure its identity, the city must banish that what threatens its unity, and specifically in this section, we are talking about Socrates’ trial and death. This discussion will remind of the later writings of Agamben in _Homo Sacer_, in which the homo sacer is he who can be killed but not sacrificed, who is completely outside of the law yet constituted by it, and he who through his exclusion allows the state to affirm is identity by contrast. The city’s “body proper thus reconstitutes its unity…by violently excluding from its territory the representative of an external threat or aggression” (133). This sort of sounds like Nazi Germany, doesn’t it? Yet while the city needs to violently oppose the outsider in order to reaffirm its own laws and thus unity, “the representative of the outside is nonetheless constituted, regularly granted its place, by the community…the very heart of the inside” (133). It is also worth noting that Derrida points out that the invective against writing is implicitly a directive against democracy. He cites J.P. Vernant who claims that the development of writing is contemporaneous with the mobilization of democracy, because writing allowed the masses access to knowledge. Plato calls democracy “ orgy debauchery, flea market, a ‘bazaar of constitutions where one can choose the one to make one’s own” (145). The fear of democracy is that it allows for excess not hierarchy, and has no real “essence” of truth but rather allows for “free” choice.

Contra Plato and the Enlightenment/rationalist view, we see that while dialectics is always directed toward truth itself, the truth must always come to terms with its own relation to non-truth: “ The disappearance of truth as presence, the withdraw of the present origin of presence, is the condition for the manifestation of truth. Non-truth is the truth. Nonpresence is presence. Différance, the disappearance of any originary presence, is at once the condition of possibility and the condition of impossibility of truth” (168). Because of this supplementarity, this failure of the ability to retain a unified original presence, the binaries between inside and outside the system cannot hold. Pharamakon really does “mean” both “poison” and “remedy” simultaneously.

As I noted above, it is interesting that at the end of Book X of _Republic_ Plato has recourse to myth. Here, at the end of this section, Derrida too tells his own myth: an imagined scene of Socrates before his death. Why? I can’t be sure, but I would argue that part of the function of this textual addition shows how easily dialectic and myth can slide into each other. Derrida uses an imagined narrative, interwoven with—what looks like—moments of a Platonic dialogue, and notes several times that Socrates “tries to distinguish between two repetitions”, which we are not sure are coming from inside or outside of his cell. Socrates monologue (is it spoken or just thought?) is stammering, following an almost incoherent string of etymologically- related words. The brief narrative ends with “knocks from without…” (171), which I think points this text beyond itself—the goal of Platonic dialogue as well as the re-inaugurated myth that ends Book X. I would argue that Derrida includes this strange textual moment, one that we can not pin-point as either dialogue or myth, or true (based on a true event) or false (but is there evidence this happened? It could have, right?) to demonstrate the ideas he has been describing up unto this point. And this takes us beyond the text, points to that which we don’t know. This, ironically, is also the project of the Plato whom Derrida has just critiqued.

Part I of Notes on Derrida's _Dissemination_



So to round out my block of reading Plato, Aristotle, and Longinus, I decided to pick up Derrida’s incredibly elucidating 1981 text _Dissemination_ since here JD engages with Plato’s infamous condemnation of writing in _Pheadrus_. In short, Plato idealizes speech as the only authentic manifestation of truth, in a turn of logic that assumes there is no gap between signified and signifier. This is the beginning of the idealization of the logos, which will come to belong only to “God.” Derrida builds his engagement with Plato’s text(s) on the paradox that this claim can only be made through the medium of writing, which it must pretend doesn’t exist. Language is always already constituted by the difference it seeks to overcome: a familiar jumping -off point for those of us familiar with the early thrust of JD’s writing. The reading of this ambiguity Derrida sees woven throughout the “Platonic text” (in scare quotes, because later we shall see Derrida demonstrates how one such unified or closed text that can be designated as the text of “Plato” is impossible) hinges on the translation of the word pharmakon, which in the Greek is used to delineate the antipodal terms of both “remedy” and “poison.” Here we come to the internal and external problematics of this term: firstly, the word in and of itself is not in and of ONE self--it literally means two oppositional things; and secondly this highlights the problem of translation inherent in the transmission of any text. For any attempt at translation must operate under the logic of binary oppositions in choosing one or the other meaning, thus effacing the difference built into the “original.” It is not that translation “adds” difference to the master text, but that the difference is already there; only now what is entirely undecidable (i.e., is pharmakon properly a remedy or a poison—note that Derrida will later use lateral associations to connect this term to an entire diverse web of meanings) now becomes “decided.” We should observe that the fact that such meaning, or truth, even needs to be decided—that is it not self-evident—points to the impossibly of the existence of any original, unified text.


To truly appreciate the meticulous attention Derrida gives the texts he is engaging with, it is worthwhile to look closer at the twists and turns of his readings here.

1. Working out the “Outwork”
From the gate, we know Derrida is saying to us, “whatever you expect this preface to be, dear reader, you will not be getting.” I said from the gate, but –and this question underlies the entire inquiry that will be this “preface”—where exactly is the gate? Is it the title, which is actually a series of titles: “ Hors Livre,” “Outwork,” “Hours D’Oeuvere,” “Extratext,” “Foreplay,” Bookend,” “Facing,” “Prefacing.” These terms do not mean quite the same thing, are not of the same “language” (French/English), and they are a mix of nouns and verbs—of name and movement. From the very outset (ha!) of “Outwork” our sense of textual origin is dismembered.

JD’s first sentence: “ This (therefore) will not have been a book” (3). There is no present (tense) in this statement: there is the past (been), and future (will not), both disguised as the present. There is no “moment” in this sentence, no manifestation of present temporality, but it is the space of the drawing together of past and future. This masquerading of a present manifestation of truth that comes to be only through the tension of a collision of past and future—this—is the problem of Western metaphysics that Derrida will spend the rest of this text (rather all of his texts) highlighting for us.

If we’ve read our Hegel (and our Marx!) we know the vexed relationship that occurs between preface and philosophical master text. Here Derrida’s preface at once prefaces and deconstructs its own logic, in what JD will term the text’s “systematic double mark.” This is a repetition without an identity, a mark that is both inside and outside the system of which it is related. This is NOT what some have termed a nihilistic negation of meaning (something like stating “there is no preface”) or some reckless “free play” that makes all terms up for grabs. It is quite the opposite-- it is true bricolage, questioning the system from within. What the double mark of this preface shows us, in its simultaneous act of prefacing and dismantling of that same logic, is that there is no real “outside” of this text that follows; no transcendental text- proper. Like a true “supplement” it is outside this so-called master text only to enhance/prepare/complete what should be able to stand on its own.


Derrida looks to Hegel’s disqualification of his own Preface in the _Phenomenology_and questions the relationship of this prefatory material to the body of the text: “ Isn’t the preface both negated and internalized in the presentation of philosophy by itself, in the self-production and self-determination of the concept” (11). What JD is calling for here is a reinterpretation of this relationship between the two texts, and an understanding why—if the philosophical inquiry is “truth” and should be able to stand on its own—does Hegel NEED to use his Preface. It’s not just that Hegel “negates” his pretext, but that it becomes both “folded in” to the text that follows and made useless by Hegel’s own simultaneous condemnation of it. It is the supplement, in both senses of Derrida’s use of this term, that which adds to as it replaces. In an interesting move, Derrida shows how the _Phenomenology_ and the _Science of Logic_ are in dialectic( “Shall it be said—this is the traditional problem—that the entire _Phenomenology of Spirt_ is in fact a preface for the _Logic_?”), and the “endless circle” (13) Derrida sees these texts engaged in demonstrates the non-distinction of any kind of “closed” master text. What is perhaps the most salient facet of this reading is Derrida’s explanation that we cannot understand the relationship between pre-text and text according to the logic of binary oppositions : “ If one sets out from the oppositions form/content, signifier/signified, sensible/intelligible, one cannot comprehend the writing of a preface” (16). Yes, Hegel’s preface is a critique of formalism that mobilizes the formal property of the prefatory apparatus at the same time. Yes, this is a paradox. But it is only a paradox if we view these texts as representative of opposition binary categories, only if we look at it through the lens of the formalist. If instead we see this as a relationship that cannot be subsumed under binary logic, then “the contradiction is rather the very movement of speculative dialectics in its discursive progression” (20). The temporality of the preface—both prescriptive and an after-effect (remember our first sentence of this preface)--is thus not a manifestation of linear time. In enacts the dialectic itself. Therefore it is both inside the text proper but always outside; it is already a moment of the text. [On a side note, I’d like to point out this textual site as a rebuttal to critics and readers who think JD is interested in simply dismantling binary oppositions and leaving things in a state of chaos or free play, where anything goes. What we see here in the treatment of Hegel’s preface is the exact opposite (for lack of a better term) because what JD makes us attentive to is that awareness of the incommensurability of binary thinking forces us to note the structure of this thinking; to appreciate the relationship between the two texts as they are constituted by the constructs of the system of language. I would argue that rather than some willy-nilly nihilism divorced from responsibility, we are made more attuned to the structure from which we read and encouraged to reinterpret it, not destroy it.]





This process which Derrida has been enacting/performing is “dissemination,” that which “interrupts the circulation that transforms into origin what is actually an after-effect of meaning” (21). Dissemination exposes the double mark and points up its dual place as both inside and outside the system. Like différance, it “opens up a snag in writing that cannot longer be mended, a spot where neither meaning, however plural, nor any form of presence can pin/pen down the trace” (26).

I used the word “performing” just above to categorize the way of reading/writing that JD provides us with here, and to that effect, I want to point out another textual apparatus that seems to fit both in/outside the “master text” that Derrida does not engage with here: the foot note. Just as he is describing the exteriority of the “postface”, the word is footnoted, drawing the reader to a two-and a half page explication of the term, where the word is defined as “adding an extra text” or an “appendix”(27). By the time the reader finally returns to the larger text –at- hand she returns to the words “ recapitulation and recurrent anticipation” (27-8), which seems to me to be the description of the process of reading the footnote that has just occurred, and the phrase simultaneously has a different function in the sentence from the “master text” to which we return. This brief slice of text seems to operate on two different registers at once. What then is the function of the footnote, another textual appendage both inside (literally, sits just below) and outside (additional information that is only placed below but yet does not fit into the trajectory of the text proper)? If he text -proper were self-sufficient, why would one need the supplement of the footnote? Derrida does not mention this as such, but I would argue here he performs again for us the same problem of constructing a binary opposition between pre-text and text, another level at which every text is thus fractured, and an example of how the structure of supplementarity he describes pervades all textual components and all writing in general.

Why is there no outside of the text ( a question begged by scholars, usually in reference to this infamous claim of Derrida’s used in his explication of Rousseau in _Grammatology_)? Because there is no inside either. Or rather, no inside that is closed off from its outside. Derrida:


“ To allege that there is no absolute outside of the text is not to postulate some ideal immanence, the incessant reconstitution of writing’s relation to itself…the text affirms the outside…if there is nothing outside the text this implies, with the transformation of the concept of text in general, that the text is no longer the snug airtight inside of an interiority or identity-to-itself…but rather a different placement of the effects of opening and closing” (36-7)


Perhaps, this sounds to some like a sort of trifling meticulousness, a sort of sly reversal of words that gives us a more “liberal” way of looking at texts. Perhaps. Until we remember that the other reason “there is nothing outside the text” is because reality is constituted by language—reality IS text: “This is the protocol indispensible to any elaboration of the problem of ‘ideology’, of the specific inscription of each text, within the fields commonly referred to as fields of ‘real’ causality (history, economics, politics, sexuality, etc)” (43). Materialism, gender studies, right or left wing politics—none of these areas are opposed to linguistics or philosophy, none offers a “cause” of ideological explanation that is not already coded by language. They are all constituted by the same system. Language is already and always political.

“Outwork” is rich with perhaps some of the most lucid and practical demonstrations of Derrida's method of reading/writing I have come across in the whole corpus of his work. And the text becomes even more valuable when we examine it in relationship to the so-called (but no longer able to be called) “master text” in the first section of the book “Plato’s Pharmacy, ” which I will dive into in my next post.